Saint Augustine’s sinful confessions reveal a lot about his
understanding of sin according to his relationship with God. Specifically,
Augustine defines his sin as seeking “pleasure, beauty, and truth not in [God]
but in [him]self and [God’s] other creatures,” (40). He clarifies that it is
not pleasure, beauty, or truth that are sinful, but it is the incorrect source
of them that is wrong. In looking at the way that Augustine derives pleasure,
beauty and truth, his sinfulness in the name of God becomes clear. It similarly
proves his devotion to his omnipotent God as the essence of Truth.
The trivial
pleasure that Augustine derives from stealing pears ignores all regard for God
as the true source of goodness. Augustine describes that this “pleasure
consisted in doing something that was forbidden,” and “the thrill of having
partners in sin,” (47, 52). Neither of these things focus on God as the source
of their goodness, and therefore this fallacy results in sinfulness. In order
to be true pleasure, it must be derived directly from God. The comradery that
Augustine takes part in while stealing pears also separates him from God. According
to Augustine, the most important relationship is with God and others are simply
a distraction. Even a wife can inhibit this vital relationship with God. “He
who is unmarried is concerned with God’s claim, asking how he is to please God;
whereas the married man is concerned with the world’s claim, asking how he is
to please his wife,” (44). In associating with others, Augustine loses the focus
on God that is necessary to goodness.
Augustine
also acknowledges beauty as the source of superficial pleasure. “There is great
pleasure, too, in feeling something agreeable to the touch, and material things
have various qualities to please each of the other senses,” (48). He notes that
while the pears he stole were not necessarily beautiful, there exist many
“dazzling fantasies, illusions with which the eye deceives the mind,” (61).
These earthly distractions may be beautiful, but their superficiality has no
importance compared to God. Focusing solely on these entities would inhibit
ones relationship with God and is therefore a sin.
However,
Augustine doesn’t entirely deny the goodness of earthly pleasures themselves.
He describes goodness as a spectrum with that directly deriving from God at the
top. The pleasures that Augustine seeks “can be occasions of sin because, good
though they are, they are of the lowest order of good, and if we are too much
tempted by them we abandon those higher and better things, your trust, your
law, and you yourself, O Lord our God,” (48). Throughout his childhood,
Augustine was far too concerned with the lowest pleasures, such as sex and thievery.
He learns that it is not these actions that are sinful in them selves, but that
they are sinful because they prohibit him from God. His newfound perspective
depicts God as the true essence of the universe. Therefore, all actions must
maintain a consciousness of God for the sake of God, otherwise they are proclaimed
sinful. Since God is “truth itself,” Augustine must strive for understanding
through actions devoted to God (61). Just as sin is contrarily caused by the
ignorance of God, this wisdom that this pure action brings will relieve Augustine
from all sin. This dynamic establishes God as a superior and omnipotent being
who wields much power over Augustine’s actions.
Ellie points out many interesting things about Augustine's understanding of sins. Especially on Ellie's points on the pear story, it was really fascinating to understand that the absence of focus on God results in sinfulness. Augustine states that "It is true that the pears which we stole had beauty, because they were created by you, the good God... But it was not the pears that my unhappy soul desired... If any part of one of those pears passed my lips, it was the sin that gave it flavour" (49). Augustine sees all of God's creations as good. Possibly, the act of using the pear for a different purpose opposed to one given by God resulted in sin. There is no focus on God, when they commit the crime, but only their own desires. Augustine realizes this places him further from God and says "I did not know that evil is nothing but the removal of good until finally no good remains" (63). Since Augustine understands God to be the source of goodness, he acknowledges that sin or evil acts take away the goodness. When that is taken away, the person becomes further from God.
ReplyDeleteBoth Liezel and Ellie bring up separation from God is a part of sin, but I think that a separation from God is what creates the sin. While preforming forbidden actions, such as thievery, are certainly disconnection from God, it seems that most actions have the capacity to bring one away from God even if they are good. Augustine explores this idea through the example of friendship and marriage (44, 48).
ReplyDeleteWhile I agree with Eleanor that Augustine's actions are sinful because they distract him from God I argue that is not the only reason they are sinful. There is a second, non-anthropocentric reason the sins are bad. This reason is discussed by Augustine in book 3. Augustine responds to a straw man question about why sins that do not appear to affect God, such as adultery, are offensive to him. Augustine responds that even though "sins of vice" cannot directly affect God because he cannot be "marred by perversion" and "sins of violence" cannot harm God because "nothing can injure [God]"(66) God is nonetheless offended by such sins. The reason is because "they corrupt and pervert... nature, which you made and for which you shaped the rules" the violation of these rule would mean humans were making "unnatural use which you do not allow"(66) of the things which God had created and ordained for them. Since God is the sole source of good, to defy his orders is to fly in the face of goodness and is highly offensive to both God and the good order of the universe he has created. Here there is a reason outside of Augustine's admittedly insignificant self for his actions to be deemed wrong.
ReplyDelete